Felix Schönbrodt

PD Dr. Dipl.-Psych.

Statistics

#HIBAR: Why Using Age as a Proxy for Testosterone is a Bad Deal.

This is a post-publication peer review (HIBAR: “Had I Been A Reviewer”) of the following paper:

Levi, M., Li, K., & Zhang, F. (2010). Deal or no deal: Hormones and the mergers and acquisitions game. Management Science 56, 1462 -1483.

A citeable version of this post-publication peer review can be found at SSRN:

Schönbrodt, Felix D., Why Using Age as a Proxy for Testosterone is a Bad Deal (March 26, 2012). Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2028882 or http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2028882

 

In their article “Deal or No Deal: Hormones and the Mergers and Acquisitions Game,” Levi, Li, and Zhang (2010) claimed that they investigated the effect of testosterone on CEOs’ decisions in mergers and acquisitions. However, they did not measure testosterone levels directly. Rather, they tried to use CEO age as a proxy, based on a previously documented negative correlation between age and testosterone level. In this comment, I argue that it is not reasonable to use age as a proxy for testosterone, and that Levi et al.’s study does not tell us anything about testosterone. General remarks on using proxy variables are given.

In their article “Deal or No Deal: Hormones and the Mergers and Acquisitions Game,” Levi, Li, and Zhang (2010) investigated the research question of whether the hormone testosterone (T) has an impact on decisions in mergers and acquisitions (M&As). Based on experimental results that T has an effect on behavior in ultimatum games (Burnham, 2007), Levi et al. hypothesized that CEOs with higher T levels should show more aggressive/dominant behavior in M&As. To investigate this hypothesis, the authors assembled a data set with 357 M&As and several economic variables related to them (e.g., the size of the target firm, the board size, and several other economic indicators). As they could not assess the T levels of the CEOs directly, they “[…] have suggested an alternative: specifically, to proxy testosterone by age” (p. 1476). Therefore, as the authors admitted themselves, their reasoning was based on a central assumption: “The validity of this approach clearly depends on the extent of the association of hormone levels with age.” (p. 1476). To summarize their findings, a significant but small effect of age on M&A decisions was found: younger CEOs made more bid withdrawals and more tender offers than their older counterparts (which has been interpreted as more dominant behavior). As the story has received wide press coverage, for example, in the Wall Street Journal, Financial Times, Time Magazine, and the Los Angeles Times, I feel the need to make some clarifications.

Empirically, Levi et al. have shown an effect of CEO age on the outcome of M&As. From the title to the conclusion of their article, however, they refer to the effect of testosterone (e.g., “[…] in M&As the testosterone of both parties could influence the course and outcome of negotiations,” p. 1463; “[…] we consider whether testosterone influences the likelihood that offers made are subsequently withdrawn,” p.1466; “This finding strongly supports an association between testosterone, as proxied by the bidder male CEO age, and M&As,” p. 1469).

In the following commentary, I argue that it is not appropriate to use age as a proxy for T level and that the conclusions of Levi et al. are taking it way too far. For the clarity of my arguments, I will focus only on the strongest reported effect. For all weaker effects, the same reasoning applies even more.

The Effect of Testosterone on Dominant Behavior is Rather Low

Is it a reasonable hypothesis to expect more dominant M&A behavior from CEOs with higher T levels? Early investigations with animals have shown a relation between testosterone level and aggressive or dominant behavior (e.g., Wingfield, Hegner, Dufty, & Ball, 1990). Recent review articles and meta-analyses on human testosterone, however, have shown that the effects in humans are rather small. For example, in a meta-analysis on the relation of male human aggression and T level (N = 9760; Archer, Graham-Kevan, & Davies, 2005; Book, Starzyk, & Quinsey, 2001), the weighted correlation was only .08. Other meta-analyses on the relation of T to dominance (weighted r = .13) and to a challenge in a sports competition (weighted r = .18) have supported this finding of a small effect (for an overview, see Archer, 2006). To summarize, if M&As are seen as competitive situations, indeed, an effect of T could be expected – but the relation is probably much less pronounced than common sense might suggest.

The Relation Between Age and Testosterone is Rather Low

The central assumption in their article is that T level can be proxied by age. How strong is that relation? A meta-analysis of 23 studies reporting the correlation between age and T level (N = 1900) revealed that the average correlation between these variables was -.18 (Gray, Berlin, McKinlay, & Longcope, 1991). That means only 3% of the variation in T level can be explained by age. Levi et al. refer to another study that shows a remarkably stronger correlation of -.50 (Harman, Metter, Tobin, Pearson, & Blackman, 2001).

All articles cited by Levi et al. report the correlation for a broad age range (e.g., 24 – 90 years, Ferrini & Barrett-Conner, 1998; 23 – 91 years, Harman et al., 2001). Given that 90% of CEOs in Levi et al.’s sample were between 46 and 64, a massive range restriction is present, which presumably lowers the correlation in that age range even more. Indeed, the scatter plots in Harman et al. (2001) strongly suggest that the correlation is mainly driven by the very young and very old participants.
But regardless of whether the true correlation is closer to -.18 or to -.50: Are these correlations high enough that age is warranted as a valid proxy for T level? As we will see in the next section, the answer is no.

A “Triangulation” of an Unobserved Correlation?

In their conclusions, the authors argue as though they had established a causal effect of T on M&A decisions. However, they had not even established a correlation between T and M&A behavior. Their approach seems to be something like a “triangulation” of an unobserved correlation by the knowledge of two other correlations. Indeed, there are dependencies and constraints in the relation of the bivariate correlations between three variables. If two of the three correlations are given (r_{13} and r_{23}), the possible range of the third correlation, r_{12}, is constrained by following equation (Olkin, 1981):

(1)   \begin{equation*} r_{13}r_{23}-\sqrt{(1-r_{13}^2)(1-r_{23}^2)} \leq r_{12} \leq r_{13}r_{23}+\sqrt{(1-r_{13}^2)(1-r_{23}^2)} \end{equation*}

Figure 1 graphically represents the relationship of variables given by this equation. The left plot shows the upper boundary of r_{12}, the right plot the lower boundary of r_{12}. As one can see, rather high values for either r_{13}, r_{23}, or both, have to be present to imply a positive sign (i.e., a lower boundary > 0) of r_{12}.

OlkinPlot_Levi_final

The left panel shows the upper boundary of a correlation r_{12} for the given correlations r_{13} and r_{23}, the right panel the lower boundary. The asteriks marks the position of Levi et al.’s study.

Given the observed estimates of r_{age,T} = -.50 and r_{rage,bid} = -.12, the range of possible values for r_{T,bid} goes from -.80 to +.92. (The position is marked by the asteriks in Figure 1.) If the probably more realistic estimate from the meta-analysis is used (r_{age,T} = -.18; Gray et al., 1991), the possible range for r_{T,bid} goes from -.95 to +1.00. These calculations clearly show that there is no argument to expect a positive correlation between T and M&A decisions. Actually, with the given data set, no conclusions about T can be drawn at all.

The Effect of Age on M&A Decisions: An Artefact?

Given these analyses, it should be clear that one cannot speak of a T effect based on these data. What about the age effect reported in this article? The authors wrote that, “[… m]otivated by the studies of population testosterone levels reviewed earlier, we use the age of 45 years as the cut-off to separate young male CEOs from the rest.” (p. 1467). This seems to be a problematic choice to me. First of all, none of the cited studies gives a hint about why the age of 45 should be a particularly meaningful cut point. None of the reviewed studies suggests a significant break or stronger decline of T at that age. Furthermore, that cut point leads to a very skewed distribution of 16 “young” vs. 341 “old” CEOs.

The strongest reported effect was that of the dichotomized variable “CEO is young” (i.e., younger than 45) on bid withdrawals. Based on the reported descriptive statistics and correlations, it can be computed that 5 young CEOs withdrew, whereas 11 did not. Concerning old CEOs, 40 out of 341 withdrew. This distribution led to the reported Pearson correlation of r = .12 (p = .02). If only one young CEO would not have withdrawn, the correlation would have been nonsignificant (r = .08, p = .13). If only three young CEOs would not have withdrawn, age and withdrawing behavior would be completely unrelated. Hence, as Levi et al.’s conclusions stand and fall on the decision of one single CEO, these results do not seem very robust to me. Why is age categorized at all? Methodological papers on the topic clearly suggest not to dichotomize if a predictor variable can be used on an interval or ratio scale (e.g., Royston, Altman, & Sauerbrei, 2006).

Conclusion

Referring to several meta-analyses, it could be shown that the relation between T and dominant human behavior is much less pronounced than suggested by Levi and colleagues. Likewise, the relation between age and testosterone, especially in the restricted age range of their sample, is presumably close to zero. From my reading of the empirical evidence, the article should be rewritten as “Age and the mergers and acquisitions game,” and it should be acknowledged that the age effect, although significant, has a small effect size.

Of course, age is not a psychological variable per se – it is always a proxy for a true causal factor: “And although it is unquestionably useful to find that a phenomenon covaries with age, neither age nor the related variable time is a causal variable; changes occur in time, but not as a result of time.” (Hartmann & George, 1999, p. 132). Hence, it would be feasible to spend one or two paragraphs in the discussion speculating about the potential causal role of testosterone (and several other age-related variables). In that article, however, from the main title to the conclusion, the authors argue that T is the causal factor. Although the authors try to rule out some alternative age-related factors, the main criticism remains: With the current data, there is no way to provide evidence for or against a T hypothesis. It’s simply the wrong story for the data.

Based on the same data set, several other articles could have been written in the same style, for example, “Bicep strength and the M&A game.” Why bicep strength? The theory of embodied cognition predicts that physical dominance is a predictor for psychological dominance in negotiations (Barsalou, 2008). As CEO muscle strength cannot be measured directly, one could use CEO age as a proxy for muscle strength (r_{age,muscle strength} =.55; Lindle et al., 1997). Physically stronger CEOs, as proxied by age, would therefore be expected to make more dominant choices in M&As. This ad hoc hypothesis has the same argumentative structure and the same empirical justification as the “testosterone story,” and the creative reader can think of a multitude of other age-related variables that might have an influence on negotiation decisions (e.g., generational cohort effects in moral values, fluid intelligence, different educational levels between age groups, time spent in marriage, or the grayishness of the CEO’s hair).

To summarize, Levi et al. conclude that they “[…] have been able to conduct that age appears to be proxying for testosterone rather than experience, horizon, or some other effect” (p. 1478) and that their finding “strongly supports an association between testosterone, as proxied by the bidder male CEO age, and M&As.” (p. 1469). In the light of the analyses given above, that conclusion is not justified.

References

Archer, J. 2006. Testosterone and human aggression: An evaluation of the challenge hypothesis. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews 30(3) 319-345.

Archer, J., N. Graham-Kevan, M. Davies. 2005. Testosterone and aggression: A reanalysis of Book, Starzyk, and Quinsey’s (2001) study. Aggression and Violent Behavior 10(2) 241-261.

Barsalou, L.W. 2008. Grounded cognition. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 59 617–645.

Book, A.S., K.B. Starzyk, V.L. Quinsey. 2001. The relationship between testosterone and aggression: A meta-analysis. Aggression and Violent Behavior 6(6) 579–599.

Burnham, T. C. 2007. High-testosterone men reject low ultimatum game offers. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 274(1623) 2327-2330.

Cohen, J. 1992. A power primer. Psychological Bulletin 112(1) 155-159.

Ferrini, R. L., E. Barrett-Connor. 1998. Sex hormones and age: a cross-sectional study of testosterone and estradiol and their bioavailable fractions in community-dwelling men. American Journal of Epidemiology 147 750-754.

Gray, A., J. A. Berlin, J. B. McKinlay, C. Longcope. 1991. An examination of research design effects on the association of testosterone and male aging: results of a meta-analysis. Journal of Clinical Epidemiology 44(7) 671-684.

Harman, S. M., E. J. Metter, J. D. Tobin, J. Pearson, M. R. Blackman. 2001. Longitudinal effects of aging on serum total and tree testosterone levels in healthy men. Journal of Clinical Endocrinology & Metabolism 86(2) 724 -731.

Hartmann, D. P., T. P. George. 1999. Design, measurement, and analysis in developmental research. M. H. Bornstein, M. E. Lamb, ed. Developmental psychology: An advanced textbook (4th ed.). Mahwah, NJ US: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers, 125-195.

Levi, M., K. Li, F. Zhang. 2010. Deal or no deal: Hormones and the mergers and acquisitions game. Management Science 56(9) 1462 -1483.

Lindle, R. S., E. J. Metter, N. A. Lynch, J. L. Fleg, J. L. Fozard, J. Tobin, T. A. Roy, B. F. Hurley. 1997. Age and gender comparisons of muscle strength in 654 women and men aged 20–93 yr. Journal of Applied Physiology 83(5) 1581-1587.

Olkin, I. 1981. Range restrictions for product-moment correlation matrices. Psychometrika 46(4)  469-472.

Royston, P., D. G. Altman, W. Sauerbrei. 2006. Dichotomizing continuous predictors in multiple regression: A bad idea. Statistics in Medicine 25(1) 127-141.

Wingfield, J. C., R. E. Hegner, A. M. Dufty, G. F. Ball. 1990. The ‘Challenge Hypothesis’: Theoretical Implications for Patterns of Testosterone Secretion, Mating Systems, and Breeding Strategies. The American Naturalist 136(6) 829-846.

 

Comments (3) | Trackback

Reanalyzing the Schnall/Johnson “cleanliness” data sets: New insights from Bayesian and robust approaches

[mathjax]

I want to present a re-analysis of the raw data from two studies that investigated whether physical cleanliness reduces the severity of moral judgments – from the original study (n = 40; Schnall, Benton, & Harvey, 2008), and from a direct replication (n = 208, Johnson, Cheung, & Donnellan, 2014). Both data sets are provided on the Open Science Framework. All of my analyses are based on the composite measure as dependent variable.

This re-analsis follows previous analyses by Tal Yarkoni, Yoel Inbar, and R. Chris Fraley, and is focused on one question: What can we learn from the data when we apply modern (i.e., Bayesian and robust) statistical approaches?

The complete and reproducible R code for these analyses is at the end of the post.

Disclaimer 1: This analysis assumes that the studies from which data came from were internally valid. Of course the garbage-in-garbage-out principle holds. But as the original author reviewed the experimental material of the replication study and gave her OK, I assume that the relication data is as valid as the original data.

Disclaimer 2: I am not going to talk about tone, civility, or bullying here. Although these are important issues, a lot has been already written about it, including apologies from one side of the debate (not from the other, yet), etc. For nice overviews over the debate, see for example a blog post by , and the summary provided by Tal Yarkoni). I am completely unemotional about these data. False positives do exists, I am sure I had my share of them, and replication is a key element of science. I do not suspect anybody of anything – I just look at the data.

That being said, let’s get to business:

Bayes factor analysis

The BF is a continuous measure of evidence for H0 or for H1, and quantifies, “how much more likely is H1 compared to H0″. Typically, a BF of at least 3 is requested to speak of evidence (i.e., the H1 should be at least 3 times more likely than the H0 to speak of evidence for an effect). For an introduction to Bayes factors see here, here, or here.

Using the BayesFactor package, it is simple to compute a Bayes factor (BF) for the group comparison. In the original study, the Bayes factor against the H0, BF_{10}, is 1.08. That means, data are 1.08 times more likely under the H1 (“there is an effect”) than under the H0 (“There is no effect”). As the BF is virtually 1, data occurred equally likely under both hypotheses.

What researchers actually are interested in is not p(Data | Hypothesis), but rather p(Hypothesis | Data). Using Bayes’ theorem, the former can be transformed into the latter by assuming prior probabilities for the hypotheses. The BF then tells one how to update one’s prior probabilities after having seen the data. Given a BF very close to 1, one does not have to update his or her priors. If one holds, for example, equal priors (p(H1) = p(H0) = .5), these probabilities do not change after having seen the data of the original study. With these data, it is not possible to decide between H0 and H1, and being so close to 1, this BF is not even “anectdotal evidence” for H1 (although the original study was just skirting the boundary of significance, p = .06).

For the replication data, the situation looks different. The Bayes factor BF_{10} here is 0.11. That means, H0 is (1 / 0.11) = 9 times more likely than H1. A BF_{10} of 0.11 would be labelled “moderate to strong evidence” for H0. If you had equals priors before, you should update your belief for H1 to 10% and for H0 to 90% (Berger, 2006).

To summarize, neither the original nor the replication study show evidence for H1. In contrast, the replication study even shows quite strong evidence for H0.

A more detailed look at the data using robust statistics

Parametric tests, like the ANOVA employed in the original and the replication study, rest on assumptions. Unfortunately, these assumptions are very rarely met (Micceri, 1989), and ANOVA etc. are not as robust against these violations as many textbooks suggest (Erceg-Hurn & Mirosevic, 2008). Fortunately, over the last 30 years robust statistical methods have been developed that do not rest on such strict assumptions.

In the presence of violations and outliers, these robust methods have much lower Type I error rates and/or higher power than classical tests. Furthermore, a key advantage of these methods is that they are designed in a way that they are equally efficient compared to classical methods, even if the assumptions are not violated. In a nutshell, when using robust methods, there nothing to lose, but a lot to gain.

Rand Wilcox pioneered in developing many robust methods (see, for example, this blog post by him), and the methods are implemented in the WRS package for R (Wilcox & Schönbrodt, 2014).

Comparing the central tendency of two groups

A robust alternative to the independent group t test would be to compare the trimmed means via percentile bootstrap. This method is robust against outliers and does not rest on parametric assumptions. Here we find a p value of .106 for the original study and p = .94 for the replication study. Hence, the same picture: No evidence against the H0.

Comparing other-than-central tendencies between two groups, aka.: Comparing extreme quantiles between groups

When comparing data from two groups, approximately 99.6% of all psychological research compares the central tendency (that is a subjective estimate).

In some cases, however, it would be sensible to compare other parts of the distributions.For example, an intervention could have effects only on slow reaction times (RT), but not on fast or medium RTs. Similarly, priming could have an effect only on very high responses, but not on low and average responses. Measures of central tendency might obscure or miss this pattern.

And indeed, descriptively there (only) seems to be a priming effect in the “extremely wrong pole” (large numbers on the x axis) of the original study (i.e., the black density line is higher than the red on at “7” and “8” ratings):

Bildschirmfoto 2014-06-02 um 08.51.55

This visual difference can be tested. Here, I employed the qcomhd function from the WRS package (Wilcox, Erceg-Hurn, Clark, & Carlson, 2013). This method looks whether two samples differ in several quantiles (not only the central tendency). For an introduction to this method, see this blog post.

Here’s the result when comparing the 10th, 30th, 50th, 70th, and 90th quantile:

    q n1 n2 est.1 est.2 est.1_minus_est.2 ci.low ci.up p_crit p.value signif
1 0.1 20 20  3.86  3.15             0.712 -1.077  2.41 0.0500   0.457     NO
2 0.3 20 20  4.92  4.51             0.410 -0.341  1.39 0.0250   0.265     NO
3 0.5 20 20  5.76  5.03             0.721 -0.285  1.87 0.0167   0.197     NO
4 0.7 20 20  6.86  5.70             1.167  0.023  2.05 0.0125   0.047     NO
5 0.9 20 20  7.65  6.49             1.163  0.368  1.80 0.0100   0.008    YES

(Please note: Estimating 5 quantiles from 20 data points is not quite the epitome of precision. So treat this analysis with caution.)

As multiple comparison are made, the Benjamini-Hochberg-correction for the p value is applied. This correction gives new critical p values (column p_crit) to which the actual p values (column p.value) have to be compared. One quantile survives the correction: the 90th quantile. That means that there are fewer extreme answers in the cleanliness priming group than in the control group

This finding, of course, is purely exploratory, and as any other exploratory finding it awaits cross-validation in a fresh data set. Luckily, we have the replication data set! Let’s see whether we can replicate this effect.

The answer is: no. Not even a tendency:

    q  n1  n2 est.1 est.2 est.1_minus_est.2 ci.low ci.up p_crit p.value signif
1 0.1 102 106  4.75  4.88           -0.1309 -0.705 0.492 0.0125   0.676     NO
2 0.3 102 106  6.00  6.12           -0.1152 -0.571 0.386 0.0250   0.699     NO
3 0.5 102 106  6.67  6.61            0.0577 -0.267 0.349 0.0500   0.737     NO
4 0.7 102 106  7.11  7.05            0.0565 -0.213 0.411 0.0167   0.699     NO
5 0.9 102 106  7.84  7.73            0.1111 -0.246 0.431 0.0100   0.549     NO

Here’s a plot of the results:

Bildschirmfoto 2014-06-02 um 10.30.12

 

Overall summary

From the Bayes factor analysis, both the original and the replication study do not show evidence for the H1. The replication study actually shows moderate to strong evidence for the H0.

If anything, the original study shows some exploratory evidence that only the high end of the answer distribution (around the 90th quantile) is reduced by the cleanliness priming – not the central tendency. If one wants to interpret this effect, it would translate to: “Cleanliness primes reduce extreme morality judgements (but not average or low judgements)”. This exploratory effect, however, could not be cross-validated in the better powered replication study.

Outlook

Recently, Silberzahn, Uhlmann, Martin, and Nosek proposed “crowdstorming a data set”, in cases where a complex data set calls for different analytical approaches. Now, a simple two group experimental design, usually analyzed with a t test, doesn’t seem to have too much complexity – still it is interesting how different analytical approaches highlight different aspects of the data set.

And it is also interesting to see that the majority of diverse approaches comes to the same conclusion: From this data base, we can conclude that we cannot conclude that the H0 is wrong (This sentence, a hommage to Cohen, 1990, was for my Frequentist friends ;-)).

And, thanks to Bayesian approaches, we can say (and even understand): There is strong evidence that the H0 is true. Very likely, there is no priming effect in this paradigm.

PS: Celebrate open science. Without open data, all of this would not be possible.

 

## (c) 2014 Felix Schönbrodt
## http://www.nicebread.de
##
## This is a reanalysis of raw data from
## - Schnall, S., Benton, J., & Harvey, S. (2008). With a clean conscience cleanliness reduces the severity of moral judgments. Psychological Science, 19(12), 1219-1222.
## - Johnson, D. J., Cheung, F., & Donnellan, M. B. (2014). Does Cleanliness Influence Moral Judgments? A Direct Replication of Schnall, Benton, and Harvey (2008). Social Psychology, 45, 209-215.


## ======================================================================
## Read raw data, provided on Open Science Framework
# - https://osf.io/4cs3k/
# - https://osf.io/yubaf/
## ======================================================================

library(foreign)
dat1 <- read.spss("raw/Schnall_Benton__Harvey_2008_Study_1_Priming.sav", to.data.frame=TRUE)
dat2 <- read.spss("raw/Exp1_Data.sav", to.data.frame=TRUE)
dat2 <- dat2[dat2[, "filter_."] == "Selected", ]
dat2$condition <- factor(dat2$Condition, labels=c("neutral priming", "clean priming"))
table(dat2$condition)

# build composite scores from the 6 vignettes:
dat1$DV <- rowMeans(dat1[, c("dog", "trolley", "wallet", "plane", "resume", "kitten")])
dat2$DV <- rowMeans(dat2[, c("Dog", "Trolley", "Wallet", "Plane", "Resume", "Kitten")])

# define shortcuts for DV in each condition
neutral <- dat1$DV[dat1$condition == "neutral priming"]
clean <- dat1$DV[dat1$condition == "clean priming"]

neutral2 <- dat2$DV[dat2$condition == "neutral priming"]
clean2 <- dat2$DV[dat2$condition == "clean priming"]


## ======================================================================
## Original analyses with t-tests/ ANOVA
## ======================================================================

# ---------------------------------------------------------------------
# Original study:

# Some descriptives ...
mean(neutral)
sd(neutral)

mean(clean)
sd(clean)

# Run the ANOVA from Schnall et al. (2008)
a1 <- aov(DV ~ condition, dat1)
summary(a1) # p = .0644

# --> everything as in original publication


# ---------------------------------------------------------------------
# Replication study

mean(neutral2)
sd(neutral2)

mean(clean2)
sd(clean2)

a2 <- aov(DV ~ condition, dat2)
summary(a2) # p = .947

# --> everything as in replication report

## ======================================================================
## Bayes factor analyses
## ======================================================================

library(BayesFactor)

ttestBF(neutral, clean, rscale=1)   # BF_10 = 1.08
ttestBF(neutral2, clean2, rscale=1) # BF_10 = 0.11

## ======================================================================
## Robust statistics
## ======================================================================


library(WRS)

# ---------------------------------------------------------------------
# robust tests: group difference of central tendency

# percentile bootstrap for comparing measures of location:
# 20% trimmed mean
trimpb2(neutral, clean)     # p = 0.106 ; CI: [-0.17; +1.67]
trimpb2(neutral2, clean2)   # p = 0.9375; CI: [-0.30; +0.33]

# median
medpb2(neutral, clean)      # p = 0.3265; CI: [-0.50; +2.08]
medpb2(neutral2, clean2)    # p = 0.7355; CI: [-0.33; +0.33]



# ---------------------------------------------------------------------
# Comparing other quantiles (not only the central tendency)

# plot of densities
par(mfcol=c(1, 2))
plot(density(clean, from=1, to=8), ylim=c(0, 0.5), col="red", main="Original data", xlab="Composite rating")
lines(density(neutral, from=1, to=8), col="black")
legend("topleft", col=c("black", "red"), lty="solid", legend=c("neutral", "clean"))

plot(density(clean2, from=1, to=8), ylim=c(0, 0.5), col="red", main="Replication data", xlab="Composite rating")
lines(density(neutral2, from=1, to=8), col="black")
legend("topleft", col=c("black", "red"), lty="solid", legend=c("neutral", "clean"))


# Compare quantiles of original study ...
par(mfcol=c(1, 2))
qcomhd(neutral, clean, q=seq(.1, .9, by=.2), xlab="Original: Neutral Priming", ylab="Neutral - Clean")
abline(h=0, lty="dotted")

# Compare quantiles of replication study
qcomhd(neutral2, clean2, q=seq(.1, .9, by=.2), xlab="Replication: Neutral Priming", ylab="Neutral - Clean")
abline(h=0, lty="dotted")

References

Berger, J. O. (2006). Bayes factors. In S. Kotz, N. Balakrishnan, C. Read, B. Vidakovic, & N. L. Johnson (Eds.), Encyclopedia of Statistical Sciences, vol. 1 (2nd ed.) (pp. 378–386). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.

Erceg-Hurn, D. M., & Mirosevich, V. M. (2008). Modern robust statistical methods: An easy way to maximize the accuracy and power of your research. American Psychologist, 63, 591–601.

Micceri, T. (1989). The unicorn, the normal curve, and other improbable creatures. Psychological Bulletin, 105, 156–166. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.105.1.156

Schnall, S., Benton, J., & Harvey, S. (2008). With a clean conscience cleanliness reduces the severity of moral judgments. Psychological Science, 19(12), 1219–1222.

Wilcox, R. R., Erceg-Hurn, D. M., Clark, F., & Carlson, M. (2013). Comparing two independent groups via the lower and upper quantiles. Journal of Statistical Computation and Simulation, 1–9. doi:10.1080/00949655.2012.754026

Wilcox, R.R., & Schönbrodt, F.D. (2014). The WRS package for robust statistics in R (version 0.25.2). Retrieved from https://github.com/nicebread/WRS

Comments (9) | Trackback

A comment on “We cannot afford to study effect size in the lab” from the DataColada blog

In a recent post on the DataColada blog, Uri Simonsohn wrote about “We cannot afford to study effect size in the lab“. The central message is: If we want accurate effect size (ES) estimates, we need large sample sizes (he suggests four-digit n’s). As this is hardly possible in the lab we have to use other research tools, like onelin studies, archival data, or more within-subject designs.

While I agree to the main point of the post, I’d like to discuss and extend some of the conclusions. As the DataColada blog has no comments section, I’ll comment in my own blog …

 

“Does it make sense to push for effect size reporting when we run small samples? I don’t see how.”

“Properly powered studies teach you almost nothing about effect size.”

It is true that the ES estimate with n=20 will be utterly imprecise, and reporting this ES estimate could misguide readers who give too much importance to the point estimate and do not take the huge CI into account (maybe, because it has not been reported).

Still, and here’s my disagreement, I’d argue that also small-n studies should report the point estimate (along with the CI), as a meta-analysis of many imprecise small-n estimates still can give an unbiased and precise cumulative estimate. This, of course, would require that all estimates are reported, not only the significant ones (van Assen, van Aert, Nuijten, & Wicherts, 2014).

Here’s an example – we simulate a population with a true Cohen’s d of 0.8. Then we look at three scenarios: a) a single small-n study with 20 participants, b) 400 participants, and c) 20 * n=20 studies which are meta-analyzed.

# simulate population with true ES d=0.8
set.seed(0xBEEF1)
library(compute.es)
library(metafor)
library(ggplot2)
X1 <- rnorm(1000000, mean=0, sd=1)
X2 <- rnorm(1000000, mean=0, sd=1) - 0.8

## Compute effect size for ...
# ... a single n=20 study
x1 <- sample(X1, 20)
x2 <- sample(X2, 20)
(t1 <- t.test(x1, x2))
(ES1 <- tes(t1$statistic, 20, 20, dig=3))

This single small-n study has g = 1.337 [ 0.64 , 2.034] (g is an unbiased estimate of d). Quite biased, but the true ES is in the CI.

# .. a single n=400 study
x1 <- sample(X1, 400)
x2 <- sample(X2, 400)
(t2 <- t.test(x1, x2))
(ES2 <- tes(t2$statistic, 400, 400, dig=3))

This single large-n study has g = 0.76 [ 0.616 , 0.903] . It close to the true ES, and has quite narrow CI (i.e., high precision).

Now, here’s a meta-analyses of 20*n=20 studies:

# ... 20x n=20 studies
dat <- data.frame()
for (i in 1:20) {
x1 <- sample(X1, 20)
x2 <- sample(X2, 20)
dat <- rbind(dat, data.frame(
study=i,
m1i=mean(x1),
m2i=mean(x2),
sd1i=sd(x1),
sd2i=sd(x2),
n1i=20, n2i=20
))
}
}

# Do a fixed-effect model meta-analysis
es <- escalc("SMD", m1i=m1i, m2i=m2i, sd1i=sd1i, sd2i=sd2i, n1i=n1i, n2i=n2i, data=dat, append=TRUE)
(meta <- rma(yi, vi, data=es, method="FE"))

The meta-analysis reveals g = 0.775 [0.630; 0.920]. This has nearly exactly the same CI width as the n=400 study, and a slightly different ES estimate.

Here’s a plot of the results:

# Plot results
res <- data.frame(
n = factor(c("a) n=20", "b) n=400", "c) 20 * n=20\n(meta-analysis)"), ordered=TRUE),
point_estimate = c(ES1$d, ES2$d, meta$b),
ci.lower = c(ES1$l.d, ES2$l.d, meta$ci.lb),
ci.upper = c(ES1$u.d, ES2$u.d, meta$ci.ub)
)
ggplot(res, aes(x=n, y=point_estimate, ymin=ci.lower, ymax=ci.upper)) + geom_pointrange() + theme_bw() + xlab("") + ylab("Cohen's d") + geom_hline(yintercept=0.8, linetype="dotted", color="darkgreen")

Bildschirmfoto 2014-05-07 um 07.14.43

To summarize, a single small-n study hardly teaches something about effect sizes – but many small-n‘s do. But meta-analyses are only possible, if the ES is reported.

“But just how big an n do we need to study effect size? I am about to show that the answer has four-digits.”

In Uri’s post (and the linked R code) the precision issue is approached from the power side – if you increase power, you also increase precision. But you can also directly compute the necessary sample size for a desired precision. This is called the AIPE-framework (“accuracy in parameter estimation”) made popular by Ken Kelley, Scott Maxwell, and Joseph Rausch (Kelley & Rausch, 2006; Kelley & Maxwell, 2003; Maxwell, Kelley, & Rausch, 2008). The necessary functions are implemented in the MBESS package for R. If you want a CI width of .10 around an expected ES of 0.5, you need 3170 participants:

library(MBESS)
ss.aipe.smd(delta=0.5, conf.level=.95, width=0.10)
[1] 3170

The same point has been made from a Bayesian point of view in a blog post from John Kruschke: notice the sample size on the x-axis.

In our own analysis on how correlations evolve with increasing sample size (Schönbrodt & Perugini, 2013; see also blog post), we conclude that for typical effect sizes in psychology, you need 250 participants to get sufficiently accurate and stable estimates of the ES:

evolDemo

How much precision is needed?

It’s certainly hard to give general guidelines how much precision is sensible, but here are our thoughts we based our stability analyses on. We used a CI-like “corridor of stability” (see Figure) with a half-width of w= .10, w=.15, and w=.20 (everything in the “correlation-metric”).

w = .20 was chosen for following reason: The average reported effect size in psychology is around r = .21 (Richard, Bond, & Stokes-Zoota, 2003). For this effect size, an accuracy of w = .20 would result in a CI that is “just significant” and does not include a reversal of the sign of the effect. Hence, with the typical effect sizes we are dealing with in psychology, a CI with a half-width > .20 would not make much sense.

w = .10 was chosen as it corresponds to a “small effect size” à la Cohen. This is arbitrary, of course, but at least some anchor. And w = .15 is just in between.

Using these numbers and an ES estimate of, say, r = .29, a just tolerable precision would be [.10; .46] (w = .20), a tolerable precision [.15; .42] (w = .15) and a moderate precision [.20; .38] (w = .10).

If we use this lower threshold of “just tolerable precision”, we would need in the two-sample group difference around 200-250 participants per group. While I am not sure whether we really need four-digit samples for typical scenarios, I am sure that we need at least three-digit samples when we want to talk about “precision”.

Regardless of the specific level of precision and method used, however, one thing is clear: Accuracy does not come in cheaply. We need much less participants for an hypothesis test (Is there a non-zero effect or not?) compared to an accurate estimate.

With increasing sample size, unfortunately you have diminishing returns on precision: As you can see in the dotted lines in Figure 2, the CI levels off, and you need disproportionally large sample sizes to squeeze out the last tiny percentages of a shrinking CI. If you follow Pareto’s principle, you should stop somewhen. Probably in scientific progress accuracy will be rather achieved in meta-analyzing several studies (which also gives you an estimate about the ES variability and possible moderators) than doing one mega-study.

Hence: Always report your ES estimate, even in small-n studies.

 

References

Kelley, K., & Maxwell, S. E. (2003). Sample Size for Multiple Regression: Obtaining Regression Coefficients That Are Accurate, Not Simply Significant. Psychological Methods, 8, 305–321. doi:10.1037/1082-989X.8.3.305

Kelley, K., & Rausch, J. R. (2006). Sample size planning for the standardized mean difference: Accuracy in parameter estimation via narrow confidence intervals. Psychological Methods, 11, 363–385. doi:10.1037/1082-989X.11.4.363

Maxwell, S. E., Kelley, K., & Rausch, J. R. (2008). Sample Size Planning for Statistical Power and Accuracy in Parameter Estimation. Annual Review of Psychology, 59(1), 537–563. doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.59.103006.093735

Richard, F. D., Bond, C. F., & Stokes-Zoota, J. J. (2003). One hundred years of social psychology quantitatively described. Review of General Psychology, 7, 331–363. doi:10.1037/1089-2680.7.4.331

van Assen, M. A. L. M., van Aert, R. C. M., Nuijten, M. B., & Wicherts, J. M. (2014). Why publishing everything is more effective than selective publishing of statistically significant results. PLoS ONE, 9, e84896. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0084896

Comments (15) | Trackback

Interactive exploration of a prior’s impact

The probably most frequent criticism of Bayesian statistics sounds something like “It’s all subjective – with the ‘right’ prior, you can get any result you want.”.

In order to approach this criticism it has been suggested to do a sensitivity analysis (or robustness analysis), that demonstrates how the choice of priors affects the conclusions drawn from the Bayesian analysis. Ideally, it can be shown that for virtually any reasonable prior the conclusions remain the same. In this case, the critique “it’s all in the prior” can be refuted on empirical grounds.

In their recent paper “The p < .05 rule and the hidden costs of the free lunch in inference” Jeff Rouder and colleagues argue that in the case of the default Bayes factor for t tests the choice of the H1 prior distribution does not make a strong difference (see Figure 6, right panel). They come to the conclusion that “Prior scale does matter, and may change the Bayes factor by a factor of 2 or so, but it does not change the order of magnitude.” (p. 24).

The default Bayes factor for t tests (Rouder, Speckman, Sun, Morey, Iverson, 2009) assumes that effect sizes (expressed as Cohen’s d) are distributed as a Cauchy distribution (this is the prior distribution for H1). The spread of the Cauchy distribution can be changed with the scale parameter r. Depending on the specific research area, one can use a wider (large r‘s, e.g. r =1.5) or a thinner (small r’s, e.g. r = 0.5) Cauchy distribution. This corresponds to the prior belief that typically larger or smaller effect sizes can be expected.

For the two-sample t test, the BayesFactor package for R suggest three defaults for the scale parameter:

  • “medium” (r = sqrt(2)/2 = 0.71),
  • “wide” (r = 1), and
  • “ultra-wide” (r = sqrt(2) = 1.41).

Here’s a display for these distributions:

 

For a given effect size: How does the choice of the prior distribution change the resulting Bayes factor?

The following shiny app demonstrates how the choice of the prior influences the Bayes factor for a given effect size and sample size. Try moving the sliders! You can also provide arbitrary values for r (as comma-separated values; r must be > 0; reasonable ranges are between 0.2 and 2).

For a robustness analysis simply compare the lines at each vertical cut. An important line is the solid blue line at log(1), which indicates the same support for H1 and H0. All values above that line are in favor of the H1, all values below that line are in favor of H0.

 

 

As you will see, in most situations the Bayes factors for all r‘s are either above log(1), or below log(1). That means, regardless of the choice of the prior you will come to the same conclusion. There are very few cases where a data line for one r is below log(1) and the other is above log(1).  In this case, different r‘s would come to different conclusions. But in these ambiguous situations the evidence for H1 or for H0 is always in the “anectodal” region, which is a very weak evidence. With the default r’s, the ratio of the resulting Bayes factors is indeed maximally “a factor of 2 or so”.

To summarize, within a reasonable range of prior distributions it is not possible that one prior generates strong evidence for H1, while some other prior generates strong evidence for H0. In that sense, the conclusions drawn from a default Bayes factor are robust to the choice of (reasonable) priors.

References

Rouder, J. N., Morey, R. D., Verhagen, J., Province, J. M., & Wagenmakers, E. J. (submitted). The p < .05 rule and the hidden costs of the free lunch in inference. Retrieved from http://pcl.missouri.edu/biblio/author/29

Rouder, J. N., Speckman, P. L., Sun, D., Morey, R. D., & Iverson, G. (2009). Bayesian t tests for accepting and rejecting the null hypothesis. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 16, 225–237.

Related posts

Comments (2) | Trackback

A short taxonomy of Bayes factors

[Update Oct 2014: Due to some changes to the Bayes factor calculator webpage, and as I understand BFs much better now, this post has been updated …]

I started to familiarize myself with Bayesian statistics. In this post I’ll show some insights I had about Bayes factors (BF).

What are Bayes factors?

Bayes factors provide a numerical value that quantifies how well a hypothesis predicts the empirical data relative to a competing hypothesis. For example, if the BF is 4, this indicates: “This empirical data is 4 times more probable if H₁ were true than if H₀ were true.”
. Hence, evidence points towards H₁. A BF of 1 means that data are equally likely to be occured under both hypotheses.

More formally, the BF can be written as:

BF_{10} = \frac{p(D|H_1)}{p(D|H_0)}

where D is the data. Hence, the BF is a ratio of probabilities, and is related to larger class of likelihood-ratio test.

What researchers usually are interested in is not p(Data | Hypothesis), but rather p(Hypothesis | Data). Using Bayes’ theorem, the former can be transformed into the latter by assuming prior probabilities for the hypotheses. The BF then tells one how to update one’s prior probabilities after having seen the data, using this formula (Berger, 2006):

 p(H_1 | D) = \frac{BF}{BF + [(1-p(H1)]/p(H1)}

Given a BF of 1, one does not have to update his or her priors. If one holds, for example, equal priors (p(H1) = p(H0) = .5), these probabilities do not change after having seen the data of the original study.

The best detailed introduction of BFs I know of can be be found in Richard Morey’s blog posts [1] [2][3]. Also helpful is the ever-growing tutorial page for the BayesFactor package. (For other introductions to BFs, see Wikipedia, Bayesian-Inference, the classic paper by Kass and Raftery, 1995, or Berger, 2006).

Although many authors agree about the many theoretical advantages of BFs, until recently it was complicated and unclear how to compute a BF even for the simple standard designs (Rouder, Morey, Speckman, & Province, 2012). Fortunately, over the last years default Bayes factors for several standard designs have been developed (Rouder et al., 2012; Rouder, Speckman, Sun, Morey, & Iverson, 2009; Morey & Rouder, 2011). For example, for a two-sample t test, a BF can be derived simply by plugging the t value and the sample sizes into a formula. The BF is easy to compute by the R package BayesFactor (Morey & Rouder, 2013), or by online calculators [1][2].

Flavors of Bayes factors

When I started to familiarize myself with BFs, I was sometimes confused, as the same number seemed to mean different things in different publications. And indeed, four types of Bayes factors can be distinguished. “Under the hood”, all four types are identical, but you have to be aware which type has been employed in the specific case.

The first distinction is, whether the BF indicates “H_0 over H_1” (=BF_{01}), or “H_1 over H_0” (=BF_{10}). A BF_{01} of 2 means “Data is 2 times more likely to be occured under H_0 than under H_1“, while the same situation would be a BF_{10} of 0.5 (i.e., the reciprocal value 1/2). Intuitively, I prefer larger values to be “better”, and as I usually would like to have evidence for H_1 instead of H_0, I usually prefer the BF_{10}. However, if your goal is to show evidence for the H0, then BF_{01} is easier to communicate (compare: “Data occured 0.1 more likely under the alternative” vs. “Data show 10 times more evidence for the null than for the alternative”).

The second distinction is, whether one reports the raw BF, or the natural logarithm of the BF (The log(BF) has also been called “weight of evidence“; Good, 1985). The logarithm has the advantage that the scale above 1 (evidence for H_1) is identical to the scale below 1 (evidence for H_0). In the previous example, a BF_{10} of 2 is equivalent to a BF_{01} of 0.5. Taking the log of both values leads to log(BF_{10}) = 0.69 and log(BF_{01}) = -0.69: Same value, reversed sign. This makes the log(BF) ideal for visualization, as the scale is linear in both directions. Following graphic shows the relationship between raw/log BF:

Bayesfactor_Overview1

Figure 1

 

As you can see in the Table of Figure 1, different authors use different flavors. This often makes sense, as we sometimes want to communicate evidence for the H1, and sometimes for the H0. However, for the uninitiated it can be sometimes confusing.

Usually, tables in publication report the raw BF (raw- or raw+). Plots, in contrast, typically use the log scale, for example:

Bildschirmfoto 2014-10-15 um 10.48.25

 

Figure 2 shows conversion paths of the different BF flavors:

Bayesfactor_Overview2

 

 

The user interface functions of the BayesFactor package always print the raw BF_{10}. Internally, however, the BF is stored as log(BF_{10}).

Hence, you have to be careful when you directly use the backend utility functions, such as ttest.tstat. These functions return the log(BF_{10}). As the conversion table shows, you have to exp() that number to get the raw BF. Check the documentation of the functions if you are unsure which flavor is returned.

Related posts: Exploring the robustness of Bayes Factors: A convenient plotting function

References

Berger, J. O. (2006). Bayes factors. In S. Kotz, N. Balakrishnan, C. Read, B. Vidakovic, & N. L. Johnson (Eds.), Encyclopedia of Statistical Sciences, vol. 1 (2nd ed.) (pp. 378–386). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
Good, I. J. (1985). Weight of evidence: A brief survey. In J. M. Bernardo, M. H. DeGroot, D. V. Lindley, & A. F. M. Smith (Eds.), Bayesian Statistics 2 (pp. 249–270). Elsevier.

Morey, R. D. & Rouder, J. N. (2011). Bayes factor approaches for testing interval null hypotheses. Psychological Methods, 16(4), 406–419. PMID: 21787084. doi:10.1037/a0024377

Morey, R. D. & Rouder, J. N. (2013). {BAYESFACTOR}: computation of bayes factors for common designs. R package version 0.9.4. Retrieved from http://CRAN.R- project.org/package=BayesFactor

Rouder, J. N., Morey, R. D., Speckman, P. L., & Province, J. M. (2012). Default bayes factors for ANOVA designs. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 56(5), 356–374. doi:10.1016/j.jmp.2012.08.001

Rouder, J. N., Speckman, P. L., Sun, D., Morey, R. D., & Iverson, G. (2009). Bayesian t tests for accepting and rejecting the null hypothesis. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 16(2), 225–237.

Comments (8) | Trackback